VARIOUS MEANS BY WHICH JUSTICE MAY BE
ATTAINED IN THE SOCIETY BEARING IN MIND THE PECULIAR NATURE OF THE NIGERIA
SOCIETY; AND THE VARIOUS DOCTRINES APPLIED BY THE COURT TO
DECIDED CASES BEFORE THEM.
Submitted
in partial fulfillment of the course requirement for JURISPRUDENCE AND LEGAL
THEORY II
LECTURER IN CHARGE
A. OLAGUNJU PHD
INTRODUCTION
A
commonly accepted definition of Justice is that it is a moral standard of all
men to one another requiring them to perform their social and moral as well as
legal obligations to each other and to grant to each other all that fairly be
granted.
Even
in our indigenous society from time immemorial, people have lived under various
notions of justice and have built their society on the principle of justice.
One of such principles is the ‘live and lets live’. Others are ‘do unto others
what you want them to do unto you and also what is sauce for the goose is sauce
for the gander.
The
importance and significance of justice can never be underestimated in the
affairs of men. This is so because according to Pope Pius XII, just as, in
fact, there can be no peace without order so there can be no order without
justice.”
The
various means of attaining justice is therefore crucial to the development of
any society whether traditional or modern because justice is the bedrock of the
confidence people have in their legal system. This question is however more
important for the Nigerian society since justice has transformed into various
kinds for various people. Justice is no longer one and the same.
In
the course of this work, we intend to investigate the concept of justice which
we will discover goes beyond equality. We further look at the various means
applicable to the attainment of justice. With particular emphasis on the
Nigeria judiciary, we shall look at various judicial attitude and conclusively
the doctrines applied by the court to decide cases before them.
THE
CONCEPT OF JUSTICE
As
soon as anybody states that a law or a court’ decision is unjust, he is quickly
met by the question: “whose say-so establishes what is just or unjust?” The
question of Justice could be said to be one of the concepts that defy
definition because of the issues it brings along with it. Such issues include:
what is just?; whose say-so establishes what is just and unjust?; how is it
determined?; is it known to all?; can it actually be achieved?, to mention a
few. Yet in spite of these sub-questions, justice is not far from what we know
it to be i.e. fairness, equality.
However,
it suffices for our present purpose to note that justice requires that freedom,
equality and security be accorded to human beings to the greatest extent
consistent with the common good. For Adaramola, the concept of Justice connotes
the legal equality of human beings i.e. equality of all citizens before the law
and in society generally for all practical purposes.[1]
Justice
is not synonymous with equality. Equality is one aspect of it, no more. Justice
is not a once and for all capture formula. It is a process, a complex and
shifting balance between many factors including equality[2]. For Friedrich[3], Justice is never given;
it is always a task to be achieved.
Aristotle
makes a classification of justice into local (particular) justice and universal
justice. Particular justice is further analysed under distributive and
corrective justice. Distributive justice is founded on the assumed principle
that there is equal distribution of distributable
things amongst equals in a given
society. But where distributive justice is distorted the judge applies
corrective or rectificatory justice to restore the pre-existing distributive
position.[4] Universal justice is
absolute justice from where particular justice gets its completeness, since it
is not possible for legal justice to cover all forseeable situations. In other
words, that which is resorted to in order to make up for the omission is
universal justice and its nature is equitable.
‘Justice
as fairness’ according to J. Rawls refers to an original position of equality
such that each person’s choice of principle in his interpretation or
understanding of the word is not influenced by his position. He states: “thus
it seems reasonable and generally acceptable that no one should be advantaged
or disadvantaged by natural fortune or social circumstances in the choice of
principles.”[5]
Justice
for Rawls is thus developed under two principles;
First:
that each person is to have equal right to the most extensive basic liberty
compatible with a similar liberty for others.
Second:
that social and economic inequalities are to be arranged so that they are both
(a) reasonably expected to be to every one’s advantage and (b) attached to
positions and offices open to all.
These
principles are to govern the assignment of rights and duties and to regulate the
distribution of social and economic advantages. He considered the basic
liberties of citizens as roughly speaking: political liberty, freedom of speech
and assembly, liberty of conscience and freedom of thought, freedom of person
with right to hold personal property; freedom from arbitrary arrest.
According
to the first principle, these liberties are all required to be equal since
citizens of a JUST society are to have the same basic rights. On the second
principle, which is applicable to the distribution of wealth and income and in
the design of organizations that make use of differences in authority and
responsibility, distribution of wealth and income need not be equal but it must
be to every one’s advantage and at the same time, positions of authority and
offices of command must be accessible to all.[6]
Rawls’
position on his two principles of justice could therefore be summed up as
follows: all social values – liberty and
opportunity, income and wealth, and the bases of self respect are to be distributed
equally unless an unequal distribution of any or all of these values is to
everyone’sadvantage.
This
notion of Justice is preferable and adaptable especially as it pertains to the
dignity of the human person. Equality in justice is not absolute. It is
qualified. This is because, borrowing Aristotle’s concepts, there are
distributable things and there are equals in the society. It is not out of
place to posit that creation itself is not just, since though we are created by
God and in His image, yet we are not equally endowed[7]. Some suffer a lot to
achieve, some do not suffer that much. Does this connote injustice? In a layman’s
view it may. However the position of Rawls takes all these into cognizance and
yet holds that there can be equality where basic rights fundamental to the
human person are involved and where wealth and income, power, privileges,
authority, are involved, justice is attained by equality in opportunities.
Eventually, no one is disadvantaged.
A
classical definition found in Book 1,1
of the Justinian Institute[8]states that “Justice is the
constant and unceasing will to render to each one his due”. Elegido[9], commenting on the
definition says that it depicts justice as a specific area within morality
since morality “tells me how I should behave towards others in order to avoid
offending them.” Based on this, the
question of whether justice is objective will lead us to the argument whether
morals is itself objective[10]. If justice is morality,
which is not agreeably objective, how can we rely on such in objective concept
to determine objectivity.
In
relation to law, a further question would be: “whose say-so determines the
justness or unjustness of a law? Again, where principles are objective,
nobody’s say-so matters. A given law
is in itself either just or unjust according to whether or not it complies with
those objective principles of justice.
JUSTICE IN THE LAW
An
unjust law damages the common good of the community. An unjust law is simply a law,
which prescribes something, which is immoral and wrongs one or more people. A
citizen’s obligation to obey a given law derives from the fact that doing so is
the only way of promoting the common good. Does the citizen have an obligation
to obey an unjust law? Aquinas states that: “such unjust laws do not oblige in
conscience, unless perhaps to avoid giving bad example or causing public
disorder…”[11]
If we
take our minds back to the Naturalists, Positive Law, to be just must meet
three requirements: it must serve the common good, its burdens must be
distributed according to proportionate equality and finally, it must be issued
by a legislator within the bounds of his authority. Where these requirements
are not met, there is unjust law. Does this give the citizen a right of
resistance against such laws in a country like Nigeria?
The
definition of justice and its attendant questions have raised a lot of issues
and concerns that one might think there is no way law can be used to achieve
justice. KayodeEso[12] in resolving this
question has said:
“For
Law to be justified in any society, it must be just. It is justice that enables
law to appear in any society as an acceptable norm or an agreeable concept, and
it is justice that could give “law” a socially and culturally high significant
meaning…it is the concept of justice, which could be attainable thereby, that
gives the concept (law) life.”
Since
equality is only an aspect of justice, the problem of justice cannot be solved
merely by treating people equally in law when in fact they are unequal. Hence,
to achieve justice, various factors other than equality must be weighed and
considered. It therefore behooves the judges to formulate principles that are
considered relevant to be applied for the attainment of justice.
MEANS
OF ATTAINING JUTICE VIS-A-VIS THE NIGERIAN PERPECTIVE.
Flowing
from the description of justice, and the various ideas of thinkers on the
subject, it is expected that these lead us to a discussion on the means of
attaining justice. Justice as a concept though elusive is necessary for the
administration and development of any society, Nigeria not being an exception.
Justice
attainment in the society is the collective duty of the judiciary and the
legislature. Nigeria being a society bedeviled with multi-cultural and ethnic
diversity is an epitome of an unequal society. This is not negative since
essentially not all things are equal or distributable. However, justice comes
as a process a complex and ever shifting balance between differing factors
including the question of inequality.
Justice
can be attained through; distributive justice, corrective justice, universal
justice and functional or social justice. These species of justice are
collectively employed by both the legislature and the judiciary.
Briefly
distributive
justice according to Aristotle is founded on the assumed principle that
there is equal distribution of distributable things among equals in the
society. This is in the realm of the legislature who through legislation
distributes ‘goods’ among equals. On the other hand where there is a distortion
or disturbance of distributive justice, corrective justice comes in to
restore and rectify the anomaly through the necessarily incidental performance
of judicial functions.
Universal
justice on the other hand, is the objective and absolute justice, which comes in to fill up
or complete any omission on the part of the legislature to make laws for
distributive justice. In other words, where new situations arise not covered by
law or where the law on a particular point becomes practically unworkable to
achieve justice, it behooves the judiciary to apply this sort of justice as a
correction of law. The judge comes in to correct the omission- to say what the
legislator himself would have said had he be present and would have put into
his law if he had known of this variety of issue.[13]
In
our peculiar nature, Nigeria has exemplified approaches to the attainment of
justice yet we are still a long way off. Justice has been sacrificed on the
altar of discrimination to the disadvantage of other citizens; merits have been
sacrificed on the altar of political expediency. Also, qualitative opportunity
to education has been sacrificed on the basis of ‘catchment areas’ and ‘quota
systems’ (in a quest to give everyone a so-called equal opportunity) to mention
but few instances. We are faced with various indigenization policies where some
state governments give undue preference to indigenes at the expense of other
citizens. Where then is the sense of justice? What about the ‘made in Nigeria
justice’ i.e. justice for the rich and influential?
Justice
demands the equal allocation and reallocation of benefits to citizens subject
to individual capacity for their effective utilization. In turn every citizen
has the duty to use his goods for the benefit of those in need once his own
reasonable needs and those of his dependants have been satisfied. The question
of justice and its attainment is a question of balance. There is a saying which
states that ‘virtue lies in the middle’. The
striking of this balance is not a once and for all attainment but the
continuous view and review to suit the changes in time and situation.
The
case of Adeyinka Bosede Badejo v Federal Minister of Education[14], where in the common
entrance examination taken by the appellant, the cut-off point for Ogun state
(the appellant state of origin) was 235 meanwhile she scored 230. While she was
not given admission, her counter-part in the other state had their cut-off
point at 189 and at such were they met with the minimum while she would have to
re-sit the examination. Such idea of justice is faulty but as far as Nigeria is
concerned it was provided in law. The Supreme court in the case held inter-alia
that her action failed on the ground that the discriminatory procedure on quota
system was made pursuant to one of the directive principles (Section 15(2))[15] which enjoins all
government to execute their functions in accordance with the formula of federal
character.
Under
situations like this, there must be a resort to functional justice. This
is the application of rules and principle of legal justice to social everyday
problem that are brought before the court and quasi-judicial and administrative
bodies. This process also referred to as social justice draws its vitality from
the sense of justice.[16] It demands that there
must be established a scheme or plan of distribution of claims and obligations
which inspires confidence and commands acceptability among the people.
The
question posed by the above peculiar instances under the Nigerian justice
delivery system is whether the various means of justice attainment guarantee a
mechanical jurisprudence in the growth of justice in Nigeria? Although justice
arbiters in Nigeria have record operational success in certain mechanical or
procedural aspects of their work albeit inconclusive, inelegant and admittedly
defective with regards to the very backdrop of the notion of justice. One may
therefore be quick to say it is a big fat NO; based on a spate of unjust
instances and examples that have demonstrated obvious practical injustice.
Therefore,
a well-planned programme of distribution must take into account all the
existing equities, i.e., the basic means, needs and legitimate wants and
aspirations of citizen both individually and corporately, it is expedient so as
to know how best to share the claims and obligations among the different and
competing sections of the community in other to maintain a reasonable and safe
equilibrium of justice within the community.
The instances
discussed in the following part of this paper will depict how the judiciary has
responded to the question of attainment of justice.
JUDICIAL
MEANS OF ATTAINMENT OF JUSTICE
LOCUS
STANDI
Introduction
As
intimated earlier, there are various synthetic jurisprudence making up the
philosophical or perhaps, jurisprudential perspective of justice. Under this
heading, for the purpose of chronology, attempt will be made to lay bare the
relationships if any, between the institutional concept of locus standi and the
administration of justice in Nigeria with its related philosophical problems.
The
term locus standi is by nature complex and technical so much that many people
tend to view it with impatience and often even with cynicism. Of particular
significance is the question whether locus standi as espoused by our courts
adequately enhance and protect the concept of justice vis a vis the various
means and methods of attaining justice.[17]
Definition
Vining
in the preface to his book asserts that locus standi or standing is a term of
art that mesmerizes.[18] It is part of special
language lawyers’ love to use and non lawyers quiver on hearing. Why? Because
it is not easy for a non lawyer who rightly assumes unfettered access to court,
to appreciate lawyers’ conception of the term.
Simply
put, locus standi is the right of a person to appear before a court and be
heard.[19]
The
question therefore is whether in private or public law, what interest must a
person possess before he can be accorded standing to maintain an action? Answer
to this question is important in that the merit or otherwise of the case need
not be investigated or determined if the plaintiff lacks locus.[20] Indeed once this question
of locus standi is negatively decided, it precludes the consideration of the
issue in dispute, thus, a wrong may be perpetuated without a remedy.
Common law position;
Notwithstanding
its sometimes elusive in character, in practical application the common law
position in relation to locus standi in general is relatively free from
ambiguity except in terms of details. The common law orthodox approach to the
concept of locus standi is that the authority of the court cannot be invoked in
vain but can only be invoked by an aggrieved person seeking redress for his
complaints. From this stand point, to be an aggrieved person, the plaintiff
must establish his interest in the subject matter in dispute under the realm of
private law[21].
It is
perhaps the realm of public law that the divergent judicial altitude in the
application of the doctrine of locus standi as remarkably manifested. This
again varies from jurisdiction to jurisdiction depending in some cases on the
type and nature of the governing constitution.
More
than a century ago, the position espoused by various common law courts with
respect to when an individual will be accorded standing to enforce a public
right is if he can show personal and sufficient interest or that he suffers
special damage peculiar to himself from the interference with the public right[22].
It is
however, noticeable that of recent, there have been strong judicial opinions or
pronouncements, which tend to weaken the orthodox approach at common law.
Particularly where its strict application may not enhance the course of justice[23]. This no doubt
constitutes a shift however slight from the orthodox rule[24]. This is a liberal
approach. But of late, the crusade for a more liberal approach has received a
set back. In Gouriet v Union of post
workers[25],
“The House of Lords asserted that it was a fundamental principle of English law
that, public rights could only be asserted in a court action by the Attorney
General.
To
drive home the point, Lord Denning’s
liberal dictum to the contrary in point
of Attorney General v. Independent Broadcasting authority[26]
was expressly disapproved.
Interestingly,
Lord Diplock was more forthcoming on the side of a wider approach to the
concept of locus standi; he stated emphatically thus;
It would, in my view, be a grave lacuna
in our system of public law if a pressure group, like the federation, or even a
single public spirited taxpayers were prevented by outdated technical rules of
locus standi from bringing the matter to the attention of the court to
vindicate the rule of law and get the unlawful conduct stopped”[27].
This view
was quoted with approval in R. v Horsham
justices by Lord Denning[28]. While there may be flash
or shift from the strict orthodox doctrine of locus standi, this shift as
remarkable as it may appear, cannot accommodate the unrestricted access to
court to any litigant who is not able to show sufficient interest.[29] The American and Canadian approach to the doctrine is not too dissimilar
basically under the aspect of public litigation.
Nigerian Judicial Approach’s
The
stance of the Nigerian court on the question of locus standi has so far not
evidence any significant shift from the common law approach notwithstanding the
aura of judicial pronouncements of locus standi in the so called celebrated
case of Adesanya v President of the
republic[30].
Ademola J.C.A rightly
noted this point in Thomas and ors v. Olufusoye; he concluded on this point and said; “to entitle a person to invoke judicial
power, he must show that either his personal interest will immediately be or
has been adversely affected by the action or that he had sustained or is in
immediate danger of sustaining an injury to himself, and which interest and
injury is over and above that of the general public. It may well be that the attitude
of the Supreme Court to the issue of locus standi is the rather orthodox
approach, happily. This court does not have to take a different position from
that of the Supreme Court[31]”.
In
the context of private law, the orthodox common law approach to the doctrine of
locus standi would not appear to have created much difficulty. As been pointed
out, application of the orthodox common law approach to the doctrine in the
area of public law would not seem to have produced consistent principles a
fortiori agreeable acceptance. The crux of the problem is and has always been whether
justice is enhanced if a person is not accorded standing to challenge the
constitutionality of a statute or to ask for a judicial review of the acts of
actions of public officials acting in the course of their duties as a result of
locus standi.
Jurisprudentially,
Adaramola in this regard termed the
doctrine as the green eyed locus standi
monster and said; the ubiquitous
locus standi doctrine, erected a virtually insurmountable barrier on the path
of social justice, and constituted a perpetual beacon of despair to those who
contemplated resorting to the courts for a redress of real or perceived violation
of their rights and interests, or those of the society as a corporate entity[32].
The
case of Olawoyin v. A. G. Northern
Region of Nigeria[33]
is perhaps the most notable forerunner of the Nigerian approach to the
doctrine of locus in the realm of public law. The court in this case Per unsworth F. J put it thus; “There was no suggestion that the appellant
was in imminent danger of coming into conflict with the law or that there had
been any real or direct interference with his normal business or other
activities… the appellant failed to show that he had a sufficient interest to
sustain a claim… to hold that there was an interest here would amount to saying
that a private individual obtains an interest by the mere enactment of a law
which he may in future come in conflict. The interpretation of the court in
this case has been reiterated by academic scholars and a spate of judicial
decisions[34].
The practical application of the above concept is a denial of access to the
litigant.
Although,
there is a shift from this case of Olawoyin
in the area of constitutional and criminal violations[35] and also in relation to
matters of fundamental human rights,[36] Consequently, Olawoyin’s
case is no longer authoritative on the question of locus in this type of cases.
This shift has been termed as the liberal approach albeit inconclusive. This
resurgence of interest in the jurisprudence of locus standi is traceable to the
willingness of our courts not to sacrifice social justice on the altar of
technicalities such as locus standi.
However,
what seems to make the difference here is absence of statutory provision
empowering any person to challenge unconstitutional or suspected unconstitutional
behavior on the part of public functionaries. Sometimes however, courts have
argued that a departure from the orthodox approach will open the flood gate of
courts to unwarranted, frivolous and vexations suits and consequently lead to a
departure from the spirit and letter of the constitution in that it does not
allow the court to concentrate on real and proper matters.
Indeed,
courts have seen the vagaries of locus standi as strong as that of jurisdiction
of the court. Obaseki J.S.C for
instance saw standi as an aspect of justiciality and as such the problem of
locus standi is surrounded by the same complexities and vagaries inherent in
justifiability[37].Very
recently, the court of Appeal in Yakubu
v Governors of Edo State[38]
and INEC v Ogbadibo Local Government
Council[39].
Both in 2014; likened the vagaries of locus standi with the concept of
jurisdiction and said inter alia: The
vagaries of locus standi is the same as that of jurisdiction therefore locus
standi or standing of a party either cloths the court with jurisdiction or
divest it of such”.
By
and large, the important question here is whether it is true or not that locus
standi diminishes the practical relevance of social justice under the Nigerian
jurisprudence? It must be pointed out that; while it seems to be generally
agreed that in deciding the question of standing, it is not relevant that the
substantive issues in the litigation might be non justiceable. It is
nevertheless both appropriate and necessary in order to wage a decisive battle
against injustice in all its ramifications to look into the substantive issues
for another purpose; namely’; to
determine whether there is a logical nexus between the status asserted and the
claims or complaints sought to be adjudicated. Such inquiries between the
status asserted and the claims or complaints he present are, per se essential
to assure that he is a proper and appropriate party to invoke the jurisprudence
of judicial power of the court rather than having a blind adherence to the concept
of locus standi at the expense of social justice.
It
is therefore rightly asserted that the range of remedies, on behalf of the
public enterprises, must be drastically widened in a society that must
discipline itself in order to survive[40]. Our Nigerian society to
say the least is very much undisciplined and a mechanical application of the
concept of locus standi under our jurisprudence will no doubt work injustice
under so many instances. For instance, as seen in fawehinmi v akilu[41] and if not for the relaxed
approach of the Supreme Court to the doctrine of locus standi, so many persons
would be made victims of social injustice and violators of the rule of law
would walk around boisterously on the street evading justice.
I
therefore conclude; it might be that at a time, the concept of locus standi had
worked to achieve justice, but various societies have developed and modified
this concept so that a blind adherence to this concept will no longer accord
with modern justice delivery system[42]. Perhaps, the view of
Roscoe pound with respect to the draconian measures of locus standi on social
justice could be used to put an end to this point. He said:
“Legal
systems have their periods in which a scientific jurisprudence becomes a mechanical
jurisprudence, given a period of growth through justice speculation and
judicial decision; there is little danger of this. But whenever such a period
has come to an end, when its work has been done and its legal theories have
come to maturity, jurisprudence tends to decay. Conceptions are fixed. The
premises are no longer to be examined. Everything is reduced to simple
deduction from them. Principles cease to have importance. The law becomes a
body of rules…… barred by barricades of dead precedents.”[43]
On a general note, if a minded citizen seeks
to infuse discipline in the society by instituting an action to challenge what
he considers to be an obviously wrongful act, he should not be randomly denied
access on the basis of the strict application of the principle of locus standi.
Thus, a wider and more liberal interpretation in the process is to be employed.
This suggestion meets the justice of the complex nature of Nigeria and serves
the interest of humanity, modern day justice delivery system and universal
notions of justice.
THE CONCEPT OF
STARE DECISIS
Judicial
precedence otherwise known as stare decisisis a procedural mode of attaining
justice.The 9th edition of the Black’s Law Dictionary define stare
decisis as “the doctrine of precedent under which a court must follow earlier
judicial decisions when the same points arise again in litigation.”[44]
This
doctrine is one of the begotten doctrines of the English Common law system to Nigeria;
it does not however imply that the Nigerian court will be bound by its English
Counterpart decisions.[45]It is a pragmatic working
formula the purpose of which is to ensure that the law is certain and
predictable as it could possibly be. For if the law must be administered with
fairness and firmness, it must not only be certain, it must also be fairly
predictable.[46]
Judicial
precedent can be classified into three broad types: original precedent also
called primordal precedent. It is that precedent which knows no other
precedent. Declarative precedent refers to a situation where a judge in
deciding a case before him states the existing principle of law without
broadening or narrowing it. Derivative precedent refers to a situation where a
judge extends the application of an existing rule so as to fit the infinite
varieties of facts in future similar cases.[47] Thus, for precedent to
operate effectively, there must be in place a hierarchical court system and a
system of law reporting so that past cases can be studied and followed.
In
the Nigerian judiciary, the law or bindingness of judicial decisions operates
from the High Court upwards in the judicial hierarchy and in the final stage,
the highest court; the Supreme Court is not bound by its own decisions.[48]
By
the rule of stare decisis, the apex court’s decision only binds courts where
the facts therein are in pari material with the one being construed in the
subsequent matter.[49]
RATIO DECIDENDI
The
material facts and the decision of the earlier court is what constitute ratio
decidendi or reason for deciding and this form the main plank of judicial
precedent.[50]
In Ajayi v. Ajayi,[51] the court defined ratio
decidendi as “principle or rule of law on which a court’s decision is founded.”
It is
the enunciation of the reason or principle on which a question before a court
has been decided. In order words it is the general grounds on which is based
detached or abstracted from the specific peculiarities of the particular case
which arise to the decision.[52]In other words, it is only
the ratio decidendi of the higher court that binds the lower court and not the
obiter dicta in concurring judgements.[53]It follows therefore that
the term ratio decidendi has two meanings:
I reason for the particular decision
II the part of the precedent which is
binding on subsequent inferior courts.[54]
IDENTIFICATION OF RATIO DECIDENDI IN
JUDGEMENTS
A
patent fact from preceding paragraphs is that the ratio is the substratum of
the doctrine of stare decisis and unless can be properly identified and
acknowledged, there is no decision for the lower court to validly rely. To
perform this staggering but diligent task, there are theories, which have
attempted to postulate how such could be identified.
(A) CLASSICAL THEORY
The
proponent of this theory postulate that the principle for which a case is a
binding authority is to be found in the reasons given by the judge and the
judge’s statement is binding only if so far it is necessary to the decision.
Hence, a voyage into the law will simply constitute an obiter.[55]This theory is demonstrably
faulty since most Nigerian courts except for the Supreme Court would naturally deliver
a precise judgement on the issues in the matter.
(B) WAMBAUCH’S MECHANICAL THEORY
This
theory simply stipulates that the ratio would naturally carry certain indicator
by performing the following exercise: (a) state those reasons on which one
thinks the judge based his decision; (b) insert a word which reverses the
meaning of the proposition; and (c) then ask whether the court would have
reached the same decision if it relied on altered proposition.[56] The weakness of the
theory is its difficulty where the ratios in a single case are more than one,
which is infact the order of the present judiciary.
(C) AMERICAN REALIST THEORY
Though
there are two groups within this category of philosophers; the extreme group
and the moderate group. The extreme group however seems to have no call on this
issue since they rejected stare decisis outrightly. The moderate group argues
conversely to that of the classical theory, according to the, to find the principle
which subsequent court will follow, one disregards the reason given by the
judge and looks only at what he does.[57] One blatant error in the
theory is that it did not take cognizance of the fact that not all the
particulars of the parties are reported in the case.
(D) GOODHART’S THEORY
This
theory seems most satisfying and it is to the effect that; principle binding on
subsequent court is to be derived from the judge’s decision in the light of the
facts which the judge treated as material. His theory according to Adaramola
lies between the Classical and American theories.
THE NIGERIAN JUDICIAL ATTITUDE
Unarguably,
the doctrine of stare decisis remains a sine qua non in the hierarchical
organogram of our courts in order to ensure the certainty of the state of the
law and its application. Hence, the subordinate court are duty bound and
without question, must abide by and remain bound by the decisions of the higher
courts. Therefore, it will be tantamount to “gross insubordination” for a lower
Court to refuse to follow and be bound by a decision on the point of law
involved in the matter before him which had already been settled by a higher
court. Indeed the doctrine of stare decisis and bindingness of judicial
precedents are the cornerstone or our legal system.[58]
The
Supreme Court gave a classical exposition of the doctrine in Abacha v. Fawehinmi when it held: “by
the time-honoured doctrine of precedent as it operates in Nigeria and common
law countries, the decision on a given issue of law handed down by the apex
court, which for us in Nigeria is supreme court, is not only superior but binds
all subordinate courts, including all courts exercising appellate jurisdiction.
It is the law that a decision of a court of competent jurisdiction, no matter
that it seems palpably null and void, unattractive or insupportable, remains
good law and uncompromisingly binding until set aside by a superior court of
competentjurisdiction.”[59] It is necessary to state
that the principle of judicial precedence is designed to ensure orderliness,
certainty and discipline in the judicial process. Where the lower court are
encouraged not to follow the previous decision of the higher court on similar
facts, such an encouragement is designed to promote anarchy, chaos and judicial
rascality which is not the design or purpose of the principles of the Rule of
Law.[60]
The
Nigeria court, at least the apex court hold this principle sacred and have had
reasons to show the extent and importance it attached to it. Thus, some judges who
have for one consideration or the other refused to follow decisions of the
higher courts have not escaped the sharp rebuke of the higher court.[61] In Enugu v. Okefi,[62] where a lower court
refused to follow the decision of the Court of Appeal, the court in the
following word handed down its rebuke for the trial court: “it is insufferably
arrogant and runs against the canon of judicial ethics to have refused to
follow the decision of this court… to say the least, by this refusal to follow
the decision of this Courton the pretext of distinction which is borne out by
the case the learned appellate judge has acted with uncommon effrontery and deservesthe
fury and venom of the Supreme Court.”
Similarly,
in Onuoha v. Okafor,[63] where the court neglected
the Supreme Court decision in the case, concluding (in the word of the Supreme Court
arrogantly)that the Supreme Court should “re-amend its position on the internal
affairs of political parties”, the Supreme Court expressed it displeasure describing
the refusal of the judge as ‘gross insubordination’, ‘judicial rascality’,
‘reckless’ and describing the judge as ‘a misfit in the judiciary’.
JUSTIFICATION FOR THE CONTINUED
EXISTENCE OF THIS DOCTRINE IN THE NIGERIAN JUDICIARY; A LOOK AT THE CRITICISMS
AND BENEFIT
The
judicial policy of stare decisis has continued its impeccable existence like a
celestial creation, although some have actuated either by scholarship or lack
of it, or some nobler and sometimes esoteric ideals of justice or some other
considerations that this dogma hinders justice, but this argument can be easily
putt off on the fact that even justice requires that the law must be
administered with fairness and firmness, for it will no longer be rule of law
if law is left to the conscience of the judges but a “rule of mind.”
Another
blow struck at the foundation of this doctrine by it very potent antagonist is its
rigidity. This contenders suggest on strong but overemphasized terms that the
binding force of precedent prevent the adaptation of law to changing social and
economic order and further contend that though the doctrine promotes respect
for the opinion of elders and that such respect may be desirable but wisdom of
our ancestors must be located within their time and age.[64] It follows therefore that
the proponent of this argument simply asserts and prefer that each case should
be decided and concluded on the believe of each judge and not an established
ruling. This will in no time lead to explosion in varying judgements and
uncertainty.
Justice
Dahiru Musdapher, a former Chief Justice of Nigeria, flayed the Nigeria
Judiciary for conflicting judgements which he believed are capable of
undermining the integrity of the judicial system, in his words he said: “The
contradictory judgements being given by our courts these days portrays the
judicial process as a game of Russian Roulette where any outcome is possible.[65] It should be borne in
mind that a court decision must be founded on law and evidence before the
court, and keeping with sound legal principles and tradition. It is not at the
whims and caprices of the judge, as per the waves of his brain and feeling.[66]The negative consequence
of this encouragement can be seen in the recent Lagos hijab ban matter where
the High Court of Lagos refused to follow the court of Appeal decision in whose
facts are in all fours but chose that of England.The tools of its existence are
simply the advantages.
The
most fundamental of the advantages is the certainty in law. In N.I.M.B. Ltd v. U.B.N Ltd, the Supreme
Court enjoined the Courts to maintain the certainty of the law. Pats Acholonu,
JSC stated that: “the theory of justice to which we adhere rests a priori on
the premise that there must be certainty and parties to the legal duel should
be in a position to know where they stand at a certain time. A system of law
where Judges of the same degree i.e. coordinate jurisdiction make contradictory
and inconsistent orders in respect of the same subject matter…each relying on
his whims, caprices, prejudices and sometimes a vaunting ego, makes nonsense
and mockery of the law. The beauty or what I might describe as the romance of
law is that just as stare decisis exercises a restraining influence on our
courts, so too do discipline in the courts in dutifully adhering to normative
order by which court of co-ordinate jurisdiction do not sit on appeals on each other,
attracts respect for the law.”[67]
Other
advantages of this doctrine are that it fosters stability and enhances the
development of a consistent and coherent body of law, it spares the judges the
task of re-examining rules of law, principles, with each succeeding case, it
preserves continuity and manifest respect for the pastu,[68] and it entrenches the
principle of equality.
If
however an antagonist still stands against this principle, then he should know
that: “to do a great right, do a little wrong”[69]
PLEA
BARGAIN
The
term “plea bargain” has become one of the most popular in Nigeria’s legal
circles in recent times, thanks to the increase in the rate of corruption-based
offences. Since it became part of the legal process in Nigeria, it has become
the easiest way out for embattled corrupt public officials.
However,
divergent opinions have been expressed as to the applicability and moral
justification of plea bargain towards the administration of justice in
Nigeria.
Concept of Plea Bargain
Plea
bargaining is a negotiation which takes place between an accused person and the
prosecution where the former pleads guilty to some of the offences which he is
charged (usually lesser offences), while the latter agrees in turn to drop one
or more of the other
offences with which
the accused person
is charged; or the
accused person may
plead guilty to
one or more
offences in return
for the prosecution conceding
to a milder
penalty.
In a
similar tone, the Black’s Law Dictionary,[70] defines it thus,
“A negotiated agreement between a
prosecutor and a criminal defendant whereby the defendant pleads guilty to a
lesser offense or to one
of multiple charges in exchange for some concession by the prosecutor
usually, a more lenient sentence or a dismissal of the other charges.’’
One
obvious inference from the meaning
of the concept
of plea bargaining
in relation to the underlying
philosophy of the Nigerian criminal jurisprudence is that once an
accused person accedes
to the use
of plea bargaining,
his right to
presumption of innocence and the corresponding duty of the prosecution
to prove its case beyond reasonable doubt abate. A guilty plea would be entered
and a pre-negotiated penalty follows. Again, any person convicted in this
circumstance cannot appeal, unless fraud can be proved or there is a
fundamental breach of his rights, just like a consent judgment in a civil case.
Origin Of The Concept Of Plea Bargain
Plea
bargaining is an invention of the American legal process, it started by
convention but having been accepted by the courts; it is now entrenched in
their federal and state criminal procedure rules[71] with the State of
California even providing a seven-page form to guide the prosecution and
defence in the formulation of their agreements.[72]
Plea
bargaining, a creation of the American criminal justice system has in recent
years gained some endorsement in Nigeria.
It is said
that an average criminal case
in America is
disposed off through
the use of
plea bargaining. In Santobello v. New York,[73] the US Supreme Court
held;
“The disposition of criminal charges by
agreement between the prosecutor and the accused, sometimes loosely called
‘plea bargaining’, is an essential component of the administration of justice.
Properly administered, it is to be encouraged.”
While
plea bargaining is
a new trend
in Nigeria, the
practice is considered
a common phenomenon in
the U.S legal
system and it
can be argued
that the American criminal
justice system would
simply cease to
function without plea bargaining.
Kinds of Plea Bargain
Specifically,
there are three kinds of plea bargain;
1.
Charge Bargain: this entails the prosecutor allowing the
accused to plead guilty to a lesser charge or to some of the charges preferred
against him or her, which typically occur or negotiated at the pre-trial phase.
2.
Sentence Bargain: is
offered when the defendant is told in advance what the sentence will be if he
or she pleads guilty. In a similar tone, Black’s Law Dictionary[74] defines it thus; “A plea bargain in which a prosecutor agrees
to recommend a lighter sentence in exchange for a plea of either guilty or no
contest from the defendant.
3.
Fact Bargain: this
kind of plea bargain is very rare in practice. It involves the defendant
admitting to certain facts in return for agreement for the prosecutor not to
introduce certain facts into evidence before the trial court.
Plea Bargain In Nigeria
Plea
bargain gained recognition in Nigeria when it was first used by the EFCC in
2005 to settle the case of corruption against former Inspector-General of
Police Tafa Balogun. It was later used that same year for ex-Governor D.S.P
Alamieyesagha of Bayelsa State for embezzlement and Emmanuel Nwude and Nzeribe Okoli
who had defrauded a Brazilian bank.
It has subsequently been used in the cases of former
Governor Lucky Igbinedion of Edo State for embezzlement (2008), and also the
case of Mrs. Cecilia Ibru, erstwhile Managing Director of the then Oceanic Bank
for abuse of office and mismanagement of funds (2010).
It
has also been subsequently used in a number of other high profile official
corruption and banking fraud cases.
In
Nigeria, plea bargaining is usually employed in the trial of financial crime
cases by making it
part of the
negotiation for the
accused person to
surrender some portion of money
which he has embezzled and for which he is being tried. This is why some have
described it as “celebrity justice”.
The Economic and Financial Crime Commission[75]
has generally defended itself on the basis of the provision of S. 14(2) of the
EFCC Act[76]
which reads inter alia:
“the Commission
may compound any offence punishable under this Act by accepting such sums of
money as it thinks fit exceeding the maximum amount to which that person would
have been liable if he had been convicted of that offence”.[77]
It is also worth noting that some have declared that
plea bargain has existed in certain statutes on criminal justice even before
the enactment of the EFCC Act 2004 in particular Section 180(1) of the Criminal
Procedure Act (CPA) and that therefore its use by the EFCC was not something
done in abstraction or without statutory precedents. Section 180 (1) CPA
provides:
“When more
charges are made against a person and a conviction has been had on one or more
of them, the prosecutor may, with the consent of the court, withdraw the remaining
charge or charges or the court, of its own motion, may stay trial of such
charge or charges.”
Others point to Article 37 of the United Nations
Convention against Corruption (2003) which says that state parties should allow
for the mitigation of punishment for accused persons who agree to give evidence
of their corrupt acts in co-operation with prosecuting authorities.
Reflections On The Use Of Plea
Bargaining In The Nigerian Criminal Justice System
The
use of plea bargaining has been vehemently condemned by some legal
practitioners and scholars, while some others have endorsed and seen it as a
welcome development in the Nigerian criminal jurisprudence. For those who argue
against the concept, it is their view that plea bargaining is unknown to the
Nigerian jurisprudence especially the federal laws. Sometime in 2012, the Chief
Justice of Nigeria, Dahiru Musdapher (as he then was), in his criticism of the
concept, reportedly said at a public lecture that“…plea bargaining is a novel concept of dubious origin. It has no place
in our law – substantive or procedural.”
As stated earlier, many people (both within and
without Nigeria) are opposed to the practice of plea bargain because it
conflicts with what they believe to be fair and just.[78]
We are of the opinion that it makes a mockery of the
institutional notions of justice. This is not far- fetched from the reasoning
(deducible from decided cases[79])
that the principle of plea bargaining
has become a dirty tool in the hands of highly placed criminals, while
disadvantaged citizens suffer the full weight of the law, when they commit
misdemeanors.
For instance Lucky Igbinedion, the former Governor of
Edo State was considered “lucky” indeed. Having being accused of looting about
N 4.4 billion, he entered a plea bargain and at the end of the day, he was
fined the sum of N 3.5 million while he forfeited three landed properties to
the Federal Government.
Diametrically, people have been committed to prison
for stealing much less than most of the public officers. For instance, a man
bagged a 5-year jail term for stealing gold earrings worth N 25,000 recently. A
young man in Ibadan was sentenced to a month imprisonment for stealing a duck
that belonged to his grandmother sometimes ago. One Idowu Olayinka was confined
to two years imprisonment sometimes ago for stealing vegetables. Nigerians from
all walks of life have since opined that ‘big
thieves’ are easily pardoned while ‘small
thieves’ are made to face the full wrath of the law.
So far, plea bargain has
tainted the image of the Nigerian Judiciary, as justice now seems to be for the
highest bidder.
It is further argued that cases like corruption, rape,
fraud and stealing of public funds should never be part of the concept of plea
bargaining. It is imperative that criminals who committed major offences be
made to serve the appropriate sentences.
Plea bargain should only come when it is difficult for
the prosecution to prove a case of corruption as a means of recovering some of
the looted funds.”
Those in favour of the practice, point to the fact
that agreements to plead guilty without having to go through a trial are
effective in saving time, costs of prosecution and reducing the burden of the
courts.
It is imperative to point out in the Nigerian context,
the opposition to plea bargain from the street is primarily due to the fact
that it seems to be used for only rich and powerful thieves and not even an
option extended to every criminal. The fact that people steal money meant for
the use of the general society is the chief reason behind the decay and
collapse of Nigeria as a country; as the absence of funds means social
amenities and welfare programs cannot be provided. Consequently, the wrath of
the people demands the rolling of the embezzlers’ heads and not merely the ‘slapping of their wrists’. Similarly,
those who make away with peoples’ bank savings are not expected to get away
lightly; the Nigerian people demand that the breach created in the public
trust, be filled up by the most appropriate and deserved punishment of their
betrayers. Criminal punishments should coincide with their crimes. No wonder
jungle justice albeit discouraged is on the increase by the day.
It is our contention that plea bargain leads to
corruption and has reduced our moral values as it gives an indication that
officials who have enriched themselves corruptly would serve light sentences
while the poor are handed long-term punishment.
Legality of Plea Bargain in the Nigeria
Criminal Justice System
According
to the Black’s law dictionary,[80] Legality means “adherence
to the law, prescription, or doctrine; the quality of being legal”.
Legal
means; “to be established, required or being permitted by law”.[81]
The only Nigerian legislation that
specifically mentions plea bargaining is the Lagos State Administration of Criminal Justice Law, 2007. Section
75 of this law provides,
“Notwithstanding
anything in this law or any other law, the Attorney-General of the State shall
have power to consider and accept a plea bargain from a person charged with any
offence where the Attorney-General is of the view that the acceptance of such plea
bargain is in the public interest, the interest of justice and the need to
prevent abuse of legal process.”
It would be of interest to also note
that some other legislation provide for a process akin, though this is
debatable, to the concept of plea bargaining. This is found in the Criminal Procedure Act and the Economic
and Financial Crime Commission (EFCC) Act, 2004.
Section
180(1) of the Criminal Procedure Act provides:
“When
more charges than one are made against a person and a conviction has been had
on one or more of them the prosecutor may, with the consent of the court,
withdraw the remaining charge or charges or the court, of its own motion, may
stay the trial of such charge or charges.”
Section
14(2) of the EFCC Act, 2004,
on the other hand, states as follows:
“Subject
to the provision of section 174 of the Constitution of the Federal Republic of
Nigeria, 1999 (which relates to the power of the Attorney-General of the
Federation to institute, continue or discontinue criminal proceedings against
any persons in any court of law), the Commission may compound any offence
punishable under this Act by accepting such sums of money as it thinks fit, not
exceeding the amount of the maximum fine to which that person would have been
liable if he had been convicted of that offence.”
In fact, EFCC introduced the concept
into Nigeria by relying on section 14 (2) of their Act. It is however our submission that
plea bargaining could not be justified under the two provisions (i.e. sections
180 (1) of the Criminal Procedure Act & 14 (2) of the EFCC Act) quoted
above. Section 180(1) of the Criminal Procedure Act deals with the withdrawal
or stay of some counts against an accused person where he is already convicted
of some other counts in the same charge and as such that cannot be likened to
plea bargaining. Plea bargaining, on its own, presupposes an agreement made at
the early stage of trial or later but certainly before conviction. Similarly,
it is wrong to equate a practice whereby a criminal charge against an accused
person is completely dropped in order to use him as a “star witness” for the
purpose of securing the conviction of his co-accused persons to plea
bargaining.
Furthermore, we are of the view that
section 14(2) of the EFCC Act, 2004, does not also, by literal interpretation
of its wordings, imply a plea bargaining. This is because the section deals
with the issue of truncating the trial of an offender by accepting some money
from him as a fine which the court would have imposed on him, if he had been
convicted, while plea bargaining advocates a negotiated agreement which is
meant to shorten the course of trial whereby an accused person makes a guilty
plea in order to receive a mitigated punishment. And in addition, as found in
most cases, he would have agreed to forfeit some portions of his ill-gotten
assets to the government. It would have been observed that, in plea bargaining,
accused persons usually forfeit sums of money running to millions, even
billions in some cases, whereas there is no law prescribing fines close to such
amounts of money.
This view is corroborated by the
decision of the Court of Appeal (Benin Division) in F.R.N v. Igbinedion,[82]
where the court, per Ogunwumiju (JCA),
held, “… plea bargain is as at now
generally unknown to our criminal justice administration and indeed our
criminal jurisprudence.”
It should be pointed out that this
court did not come to this position without considering the provisions of the
Criminal Procedure Act (which has the same wordings as the Criminal Procedure
Law quoted above) and the EFCC Act.
Conclusively; It may be conceded
that plea bargaining hastens the process of criminal prosecution as it also
enables the federal government, most especially, to retrieve stolen public
funds. It is nonetheless a concept that is alien to the Nigerian criminal
jurisprudence, though with the exception of Lagos State law.
We do not see the justice in the modus operandi of
plea bargain in Nigeria as that is a door left open for abuse. When a crime is
committed against a society, there should be deterring punishments, and to our
mind, plea bargain is not one of such deterrents.”
In the opinion of most Nigerians, plea bargain has
become the avenue being explored by corrupt government officials to escape just
punishment for their criminal acts. One of the many disadvantages is that it
sometimes puts the prosecution at a disadvantage, especially at the bargaining
table. The offender sometimes has the effrontery to dictate which assets to
give up.
Of course plea bargaining has also opened the eyes of
corrupt Nigerians. It is our humble submission that it has become an
encouragement to steal as much as can be stolen knowing fully well that after
pleading guilty, a part of it would be taken away while the rest would be
enjoyed without any disturbance. As such, Nigeria’s struggle to attain a
corruption-free environment may continue for a while as public officials seem
to have seen a new avenue of evading heavy punishments for financial crimes.
Lastly, it operates in Nigeria as a mockery of the institutional notions of
justice.
STATUTORY
INTERPRETATION
In
the course of attainment of justice, the judiciary has postulated tools, which
have, stand the test of time, one of which is the mode of interpretation of
statute. These rules of interpretation are usually referred to as the canons of
interpretation.
It is
generally accepted that words have no proper or specific meaning until they are
put into a context of situation and would also depend on the operative
intention of the particular user. Hence as Lord Denning puts it “English
language is not an instrument of mathematical precision.”[83]
Thus
as a result of the uncertainty over the meaning of words, statutory
interpretation has been described as a non-subject[84]. Thus statutory
interpretation is one of the cardinal functions of the courts and it is of
compelling necessity[85]. Hence in view of this
role by judges of interpreting or construing statutes, Lord Devlin has
concluded that, “the law is what the judges say it is”. The court must not
bring to bear on the provisions of the statute its prejudices as to what the
law should be, but rather should
interpret the law from clear words used by the legislature. Hence the
court must not amend the statute to achieve a particular object or result[86]. Thus, the practical
effect of this role which the judges play in interpreting vague and ambiguous
statutory provision is the consequence that arises from the fluid nature of the
words used by the legislative draftsman.
Thus,
the judges are concerned with discovering the true “intention” of parliament or
of the legislator in order to give effect to the law,[87] i.e., to conjecture what
parliament or of the legislators intend or what their own intention would have
been had they been the parliament. Hence in construing a statute, every word or
clause in an enactment must be read together; not in isolation but with
reference to the context and other clauses in the statute in order, as much as
possible, not only to reach a proper legislative intention, but also to make a
consistent meaning of the whole statute[88]. In ascertaining the intention
of the legislator, the courts have developed rules and principles, which would
aid them in this regard. The following basic rules are resorted to;
The Literal Rule
This
rule is predicated on the precise wordings of the statute. If the exact words
used in a statute are plain and unambiguous, then they are bound to be
construed on the strength of there natural meaning in ordinary sense. This mode
of interpretation has received judicial imprimatur in Umar Ardo v. MurtalaNyako where the Supreme Court base on sound
principle of judicial policy held that: “it is settled law that in the
interpretation of statutes, the words used, in as much as they are clear and
unambiguous, must be given their ordinary meaning, unless this would lead to
absurdity or be in conflict with other provisions of the statute.”[89] This approach is also
known as the “plain meaningrule.”[90]
The
court are not allowed to derogate from the intentions of the legislature where
the words of a statute are certain, plain and unambiguous and where they do not
attract any other context other than their plain and natural meanings.[91] The literal rule may
therefore be regarded as expressing an irrefutable presumption, that the
legislature intends the ordinary and natural meaning of the words it employs.
The Golden Rule
The
golden rule allows a judge to depart from a words normal meaning in order to
avoid an absurd result. The reasoning behind this rule, since the concern of
judges is to discover the real intention of parliament or legislator, and since
it will be improper to ascribe to parliament or the legislator an intention to
perpetrate injustice in society. Thus according to this rule, where the
ordinary meaning of words would be “at variance with the intention of the
legislator or lead to a manifestation of injustice or absurdity or repugnancy,
the language may be varied or modified so as to remove the absurdity or repugnancy.”[92]
The Mischief Rule
The
main aim of this rule is to determine the “mischief and defect” that the
statute in question has set out to remedy, and what ruling would effectively
implement this remedy. Thus using this rule, the court is able to consider the
policy and purpose of the statute under construction. This is why the rule is
often referred to as “purposive
rule”.
The rule was formulated in Heydons’ case[93] and it’s the oldest of
the three main rules of statutory interpretation. Thus where a statutory
provision is ambiguous, the court is to consider four things, viz;
a)
The pre-existing law or
situation before the act being construed was passed;
b)
The defect or mischief
not covered by the pre-existent law or which was found in the pre-existing
situation;
c)
The remedy prescribed
by parliament or the legislator to remove the defect or mischief;
d)
The true reason for the
remedy[94].
The judge,
thereafter the consideration of the above, is to make such construction as
shall suppress the defect or mischief and advance the remedy prescribed by the
Act.
Auxiliary
Rules of Statutory Interpretation
Apart from the
main rules or canons of interpretations above, other auxiliary rules usually
relied on by judges to solve the problem of ambiguities in statutes include;
a)
The ExpressioUnius Est Exclusion Alterius rule:
In the rule of
statutory interpretation, the principle is settled that in construction of
statutory provisions, where specific things or persons are mentioned, the
intention is that those not mentioned are not intended to be included[95].
b)
The
Noscitur a Sociis rule:
This rule means
that where words of doubtful meaning occur in a statue, their meaning may be
clarified from the context in which it is used. Thus it is a rule of language
used by the courts to help interpret legislations, under which the questionable
meaning of a doubtful word can be derived from its association with other
words.
Thus in the case
of Foster v DiphwysCasson[96] which involved a statute which stated that explosive’s taken
into a mine must be in a “case or canister”. Here the defendants used a cloth
bag. The courts had to consider whether a cloth bag was within the definition.
Under noscitur a sociis, it was held that the bag could not have been within
the statutory definition, because parliament’s intention was referring to a
case or container of the same strengths as a canister.
c)
The
Eiusdem Generis Rule:
This rule of
interpretation connotes that where particular words are followed by general
words, the general words are to be limited to the same kind as the particular
words. However, there must first be a category specified before the presumption
can apply[97].
The rule was applied in Awolowo v.
Federal Ministry of Internal Affairs[98] where the court had to
interpret sections 21(5)(c) of the Constitution of the federal republic of
Nigeria which provided a right for an accused person “to defend himself in
person or by legal representative of his choice”. The court held that under the
provision, if the legal representative is outside Nigeria, he must be a person
who could enter Nigeria as of right and is under no disability.
Statutory Aids To The Interpretation
Of Statutes
Basically, there are two aids under
this heading; they are;
I.
Intrinsic Aids
II.
Extrinsic Aids
Extrinsic aids to interpretation consist of everything not
found within the statute, whereas intrinsic aids are those found within the
statute being interpreted. The use of extrinsic aids thus implies non-adherence
to literalism.
Criticism
of Rules of Statutory Interpretation
The rules of statutory
interpretation have been attacked as inconsistent, uncertain, and undesirable,
both in what they say and how the courts apply them. Some of these criticisms
have been directed at the rules generally, others at only certain types of
rules, especially the plain meaning rule and those rules pertaining to the use
of extrinsic aids in the interpretive process.If such attacks are justified, then
the effect of statutes is unpredictable, because there is no way of telling in
advance what rules of interpretation a court will choose to follow or ignore.
The law of statutory interpretation
becomes a bag of tricks from which courts can pull respectable-sounding rules
to justify any possible result that the judges desire.
This law also provides a cover
behind which judges can hide to avoid carefully thinking through solutions to
the problems before them, or to avoid declaring the real reasons for their
decisions.
It encourages laziness and hypocrisy
on the part of the bench and it weakens the discretionary pragmatism of judges
towards the attainment of justice. A practical example of this situation was
demonstrated in the memorable pronouncement of Honourable Justice Mohammed
Bello[99]
which he made ex cathedra. He said inter-alia:
“Justice,
that is theoretical. We don’t do justice. We do justice according to the law;
we pass judgments which do not comply with our conscience.[100]
In reiterating
Chief Bello’s stand, a Cartoonist, Osazuwa Osagie has vividly portrayed the
predicament of a judge in such circumstances. In the said cartoon, Osagie has
depicted a judge who was passing a sentence on the accused to have said:“I believe you are innocent; but the law says
you are guilty as charged.[101]
The blunt view
of Chief Justice Mohammed Bello buttresses the point that the Nigerian judge
cannot bend the law to do justice to the extent that an England judge can bend
the law in England.
Literal
Rule of Construction: Criticism
It is worthy to note primarily at
the outset that different schools of thought have overwhelmingly argued for the
continued existence of the literal approach to statutory interpretation as it
undeniably promotes the certainty in the law which is one of the chief
objectives of any legal system. However, certain criticisms have trailed this
judicial attitude.
The
most fundamental objection to the rule is that it is based on a false premise
namely that words have plain ordinary meanings apart from their context. Prof
H.L.A Hart of Oxford has argued that a word has a core meaning or standard
instance in which no doubts are felt about its application even though at the
edges there is a margin of uncertainty. But Professor Lon Fuller has contested
this by urging that meaning attaches not to individual words but to sentences
and paragraphs, and that 'surely a paragraph does not have a "standard
instance" that remains constant whatever the context in which it appears.
If a statute seems to have a core meaning 'this is because we can see that,
however one might formulate the precise objective of the statute, this case
would still come within it. The plain-meaning theory may be acceptable outside
the courtroom, since it could be true that a high proportion of statutory
materials and other legal documents can in fact be interpreted without recourse
to any mischief or golden rule. But in the court room there are by definition
two parties, usually represented by counsel, arguing over the meaning of the
relevant passage. It makes little sense to dispose of the issue between them by
reference to the plain meaning when there are two meanings in issue.
The
literalist approach makes too little allowance for the natural ambiguities of
language, for the frailties of even the most skilled of draftsmen and for the
impossibility of foreseeing future events.
It is
open to debate that to place undue emphasis on the literal meaning of the words
of a provision is to assume an unattainable perfection in draftsmanship; it
presupposes that the draftsmen can always choose words to describe the
situations intended to be covered by the provision which will leave no room for
a difference of opinion as to their meaning. Such an approach ignores the
limitations of language, which is not infrequently demonstrated even at the
level of the House of Lords where Law Lords differ as to the so-called 'plain
meaning' of words.
The
literal approach is based on a narrow concentration on the actual words used,
to the exclusion of the surrounding circumstances that might explain what the
words were actually intended to mean.
A
final criticism of the literal approach to interpretation is that it is
defeatist and lazy. The judge gives up the attempt to understand the document
at the first attempt. Instead of struggling to discover what it means, he
simply adopts the most straightforward interpretation of the words in question
- without regard to whether this interpretation makes sense in the particular
context. It is not that the literal approach necessarily gives the wrong result
but rather that the result is purely accidental. It is the intellectual
equivalent of deciding the case by tossing a coin. The literal interpretation
in a particular case may in fact be the best and wisest of the various
alternatives, but the literal approach is always wrong because it amounts to an
abdication of responsibility by the judge. Instead of decisions being based on
reason and principle, the literalist bases his decision on one meaning arbitrarily
preferred.
Other possible methods of Statutory
Interpretation
1.
The
Social policy approach: This is to the effect
that the judge should give or attach significant weights to the subjective
purpose of the legislature and adhere less to the formal rules of
interpretation. There is no democracy without a recognition of the values and
principles that shapes it. The judges must rely on the fundamental values in
the interpretation of the legislation. By doing so the judge gives the statute
a dynamic meaning and thus bridges the gap between law and the society.
2.
The
free intuition approach: The whole gist about
this approach is that it argues for the creativity capacity of judges in
interpreting exceptional cases.
Practically,
to demonstrate the relevance of this theory under the present day reality, the
following analogy will not be out of place;
“if for instance a man plying the highway
becomes alerted either by traffic signs or by other means that there is an
impending danger at the approaching end and under compulsory or human tension
he decides to take a U-turn against traffic rules thereby violating the laws of
the land. If such person is apprehended in the process and taken before the
court, the Nigerian jurisprudence will no doubt leave the judge with no other
option than to convict the accused regardless the fact that his transgression
was done under a super-normal or an abnormal circumstance”.
Based
on the above analogy, the philosophical question is whether social justice
would be enhanced by punishing such a victim for such an offence or whether the
free intuition policy will allow the judge to use his discretionary pragmatism
to avail the victim having regard to the circumstance under which the accused
had acted?
CONCLUSION
On the
whole, so that one would not have a blind adherence to a verbal formula without
regards to its consequences, the above exposition of justice and the various
means through which it could be attained in Nigeria with vibrant postulations
on their pit-falls and recommendations therefore behooves the relevant
authorities administering same to exercise sound and careful pragmatism towards
its improvement.
Our humble
charge therefore to all those who are connected with the dispensation of
justice is that we resolve in our minds at all times, with all honesty, that at
the end of our stewardship in the citadel of justice, we shall find ourselves
in a position to say truly that:
“We have found justice dear and
we helped in making it cheap; found it in a sealed book, assisted in living it
in a living letter; found it in the patrimony of the rich, joined it in the
inheritance of the poor.”
This is in tune with the institutional and
universal notions of justice, we submit with respect.
BIBLIOGRAPHIES
Adaramola basic jurisprudence
(Put others)
[1]
See Adaramola JURISPRUDENCE, Fourth Edition: lexis Nexis 2008. P.197.
[2]
Dias Jurisprudence, Fifth Edition.Butterworths: 1985 p. 66
[3] Friedrich ‘Justice: the Just
Political Act’ 6 Nomos, Justice, at 34 in Dias
Jurisprudence. P.66.
[4] Ibid. emphasis mine. This raises a question
that Some things are distributable and others are not. As equal distribution
will not cover all goods(things). Also, Aristotle’s position regarding equals
suggests that justice is not possible. He states that Justice is only equality
among equals and that inequality is just but only among unequals. As such,
equals should be treated equally and unequals unequally.
[5] John Rawls: A Theory of Justice
(Revised Ed. 1999) in LLOYDS Introduction to Jurisprudence. 8th
Edition M.D.A. Freeman (Sweet & Maxwell) 2008
[6] Ibid. pp. 632 -635
[7]
It is a self evident fact, that
inspite of legal equality, it is actually impracticable to distribute things
perfectly equally amongst citizens, eventhough it is a desirable goal. –
Adaramola p.199
[8]
J.M Elegido JURISPRUDENCE. Spectrum Law Series (2000)p.360
[9]
Ibid.
[10] However, there are arguments in
favour of the existence of objectively valid moral principles and norms.
[11] Summa Theologiae I- II q.96,
a.4c.
[12] J. Eso, “Wither Nigerian
Jurisprudence, Volkgeist?” Lecture delivered at the Faculty of Law, University
of Ibadan, March 1986. Cited in I.E. Sagay, A
Legacy for Posterity: The Work of the Supreme Court (1980-1988)
(Lagos,1988), p.119
[13] See Adaramola, pg.
197
[14] (1988) suit No; M/500/88 Appeal No: CA/L/405/88
(1990); 2 WBRN 48 CA
[15] 1979 Constitution of the Federal Republic of
Nigeria
[16] Adaramolapg 207
[17] See preceding analysis for the methods and
means of attaining justice
[18] in his book entitled “Legal Entity”
[19] Thomas v. Olufusoye (1986) 2 SC 325 at 380;
Baker v Car(1969) US 186 at 204
[20]
Gamioba&Ors v. Esezi (1961) 1
AII NLR 568 at 588; ogunsanya v. Audu (1982) 3 NCLR 529 at 537
[21]
See Fatayi Williams C.J.N in Adesanya v. President of Nigeria (1981) 2
NCLR 358
[22] See Buckley J. in Boyce v. Paddington Borough
Council (1903) 1 ch. 109 at 114.
[23] R. v Paddington (1966) 1 QB 380 at 400-401.
[24] R v Commissioner of Police (1968) 2 QB
118-122.
[25] (1977) 3 ALL ER 70.
[26] (1973)
1 ALL ER 689 at 696-99
[27] Ibid
[28] (1982)
2 ALL ER 269 at 282
[29]
Spates of judicial decisions under the common law jurisdiction have demonstrated
this point.
[30] (1981)
1 ALL N.L.R. 32
[32] Basic jurisprudence (4th ed.) by
FunshoAdaramola pg. 245
[33] (1961) ALL N.L.R. 269
[34] RansomeKuti v. A.G. Federation (1985) LPELR-
SC 123/1984; and a host of others.
[35] See. Fawehinmi v. the president
(2007) 14 NWLR (pt. 1054) 275; also Ganifawehinmi
v. Akilu(1987) 4 NWLR (pt. 67) 767
[36]
S. 46(1) Constitutional of the Federal Republic of Nigeria 1999 (as
amended); also, the provisions in the FREP RULEs 2009
[37] Adesanya’s case (supra)
[38] (2014) LPELR 22810 (CA)
[39] (2014) LPELR 22810 (CA)
[40] W.friendmann, Law in a changing society (2nded)
p. 432
[41] (supra)
[42] Now, the right to bring a
private prosecution has existed and has formed part of the laws of many
countries. For instance, see; Halsbury;s laws of England 4th
Edition; vol 11 para97 (1976); also, See Lord Diplock’s dictum on the concept
of locus standi (ibid);
[43] Roscoe Pound, “the liberty
of contracts”. [1909] 18 Yale L:j 454
[44] Bryan A. Garner p. 1537
[45] A.G Bendel State v. A.G
Federation (1981) 10 SC 1 at p. 187-188, Eso JSC: “gone should be the days, if
ever they were, when the decisions of the courts in any common law country are
to be accepted in this country as precedent in the like of Delphic Oracle. The
decisions of any court, other than those of this court, are only to be treated
as the respected opinions of those courts, which were given in their wisdom,
under given circumstances and given environmental and cultural background, no
more. They are at best, to give guidance of what those courts did in those
circumstances, and the wisdom to be drawn from them by this Court would be
reflected in its dealing with the peculiar problems of this country, to which
the Constitution which this country operates, is peculiar.”
[46]FunsoAdaramola’s Jurisprudence,
4h edition LexisNexis publications, p. 222
[47] Ephraim A. Ikegbu, S. A Duru and
Dafe Emmanuel, Rationality of Judicial Precedent In Nigeria’s Jurisprudence,
American Journal of Contemporary Research Vol. 4, No. 5; May 2014 at p. 150
[48]
Buckor-Macleen v. Inlaks Ltd (1980) 8 – 11 S.C 1.
[49] Abu v. Adegbo (2001) 41 W.R.N. 1; Emordi v.
Kwentoh (1996) 2 NWLR (pt. 433) 656 SC; Ladele v. Aromolaran II (1996) 6 NWLR
(pt. 453 180 SC
[50] j. oAsein, Introduction To Nigerian Legal
System, 2nd edition 2005 at p. 75; FRN v. Lawani (2013) LPELR-20376
(CA); National Electric Power Authority v. Onah (1997) 1 N.W.L.R 680
[51] (2014) LPELR-22471 (CA)
[52]
Ajibola v Ajadi (2004) 14 NWLR (pt. 892) p. 14 at 21
[53]
Abacha v Fawehinmi (2000) A SC (pt. II)
[54]
FunsoAdaramola’s Jurisprudence, 4th edition LexisNexis publications, p.
224
[55] ibid.
[56] ibid.
[57] ibid. at 226
[58]Abaye v. Ofili (1986) 1 NSCC 94;
Chief Aliu Abu &Ors v. Chief AbubakarZibiriOdugbo&Ors (2001) 7 SCNJ
170; Dalhatu v. Turaki (2003) 15 NWLR (pt. 843) 310; L.M.B Ltd v. P.T.F. (2006)
5 NWLR (pt. 974) 463 at 478; LawaniAdesokan&Ors v. Sunday Adetunji&Ors
(1994) 5 NWLR (pt. 346) 540; Osemwingie&Ors v. Osemwingie&Ors (2012)
LPELR-19790 (CA)
[59] (2000) 6 NWLR (pt. 660) 224;
Igbani v. Bayelsa State INEC (2013) LPELR-21239; Babatunde and Anor v. Olatunji
and Anor (2000) 2 NWLR (pt. 646) 557
[60] Per Onnoghen J.S.C Ardo v. Nyako
(2014) LPELR-22878 (SC) at Pp 43-44
[61] Enhancing Transparency In The
Nigerian Judicial Process: The Need To Adhere To The Rule Of Stare Decisis,
text of paper presented by Chief Akin Olujimi SAN to the Civil Litigation
Committee of the Section on Legal Practice of the N.B.A at the N.B.A Annual
Conference held in Lagos from 17th to 23rd August, 2009
[62] (2000) 3 NWLR (pt. 650) 620 at 639
[63] (1982) 2 SCNLR 244
[64] Ephraim A. Ikegbu, S. A Duru and
Dafe Emmanuel, Rationality of Judicial Precedent In Nigeria’s Jurisprudence,
American Journal of Contemporary Research Vol. 4, No. 5; May 2014 at p. 152
[65] As a remark at the maiden
National Monthly Law Reform Lecture themed: Judicial Precedence; Taming the
Common Law” on 07th June 2012
[66]
Ogolo v. Ogolo (2006) 5 NWLR (pt. 852) 494
[67] (2004) 12 NWLR 12 (pt. 888) 599
[68] Director General, State Security Services v.
Ojukwu (2006) 13 NWLR (pt. 998) 575
[69] Merchant
of Venice Act 3, Scene 1
[70] 9th
Edition (2009)
[73] (1971) 404 U.S 257, 260 [92 S. Ct. 495, 498
[74] 9th Edition
[75] Hereinafter referred to as ‘EFCC’
[76] 2004
[77] S.
14(2) Economic and Financial Crimes Commission (Establishment) Act. CAP E1 LFN
2004
[78] See Onyema, Emmanuel; “EFCC AND PLEA BARGAIN
ISSUE IN NIGERIA: MATTERS ARISING”: The Crime Free & Peace Initiative.
[79] For instance, former
Inspector General of Police, TafaBalogun who converted billions of Naira
belonging to the Police Force for personal use was handed a six-month jail term
for each of the eight counts brought against him as well as a fine of N 500,000
for each count. The terms were however to run concurrently while the judge also
ordered that the 67 days he spent in detention during the trial should be
deducted. In Balogun’s case, after sessions of plea bargaining, the multitude
of offences he was alleged to have committed, including registering phoney
companies, into whose accounts police funds were allegedly diverted and later
withdrawn were collapsed into 8 counts. Though the former Inspector General
lost a number of assets and paper money which were seized from him, the
sentence he got was described by many as a “slap on the wrist”.
[80] 9th Edition
[81] Ibid
[83] See: Seaford Court Estate Ltd v. Asher (1949) 2 KB,481, 498,499
[84] Prof. LawerenceAtsegbua, “The Supreme Court
Doctrine In The Interpretation And Construction Of Statute”: The Vanguard
Newspaper, June 14, 2012.
[85]
Adaramola, “Book Review”: Maxwell On Interpretation Of Statutes, 11
(1970) 4 Nigerian Lj.
[86]
Basinco Motors Ltd. v. Woermann Line &Anor (2009) 13 NWLR (Pt.1157)
149 As Per Adekeye, Jsc At 189-190 H-A
[87] Onasile V Sami (1962) 1 All NLR 272
[88] The State V Governor Of Osun State &Ors
(2006) LPELR-11771 (CA)
[89] (2014) LPELR-22878 (SC) p. 46; Nicholas
ChukwujekwuUkachukwu v. Peoples Democratic Party & 3 Ors [2014] LerSc 589/2013
[90] (1963) 3 All ER 544 (Pc)
[91] See Federal University Of Technology &Ors
v. Academic Staff Union (2013) LPELR-20323 (CA)
[92] Awo v. UsmanSarki (1962) NLR 178
[93]
(1584) 3 Co. Rep. 7(A) & (B)
1 All NLR 129
[94]
International Bank For West Africa Ltd v. Imano (Nig.) Ltd &Anor
(1988) 3 NWLR. (Pt. 85), 633 At 668
[95]
Oluwalogbon V. Government Of United Kingdom And Anor (2005) LPELR-1131
(CA)
[96]
(1887) Q.B.D 428
[97] A.G Cross River State V Esin (1991) 6 NWLR
Pt.197, P.365 Ca.
[98]
(1962) Llr 177.
[99]
Immediate past Chief Justice of
Nigeria
[100] Mohammed Bello, CJN., ‘My Idea of Justice’ (an
interview). ‘African Concord, December
18, 1989 Vol. 4 No 34 page 45. Quoted with approval by Livy Uzuokwu in the
Article titled; ‘The Grundnorm, a Critical Appraisal’, published in Justice, October Edition 1990 page 85 at
page 86.
[101]
Livy Uzuokwu, op. cit., at page
90